Forced
Into Glory: Lincoln Revisionism
By
Lucas E. Morel
Lerone
Bennett, Jr. Forced
Into Glory: Abraham Lincoln's White Dream
(Chicago:
Johnson Publishing Company, 2000); $35.00; 652 pp.
Lerone
Bennett, Jr. published an article in the February 1968
issue of Ebony magazine that asked, “Was Abe Lincoln a
White Supremacist?” He answered in the affirmative.
Thirty-two years later, Ebony’s
executive editor has expanded his six-page critique into
a book more than 600-pages in length. As the new title
suggests, Bennett argues that Lincoln was “forced into
glory” against his personal and political wishes by
“the real emancipators,” black and white
abolitionists (among others), to whom Bennett dedicates
his book. At the heart of his revisionist appraisal of
Lincoln’s legacy is the claim that the Emancipation
Proclamation did not free a single slave, nor was it
Lincoln's intention to do so. If the “great
emancipator” had his way, Bennett adds, he would have
instigated “the racial cleansing of the United States
of America.”
Where
to begin? Never has so much been so wrong about so
important a subject. The only way to misrepresent
Lincoln more would be to misspell his name. Add to this
Bennett’s denigration of George Washington, Thomas
Jefferson, Booker T. Washington, Winston Churchill,
Ronald Reagan, and conservatism generally, along with
frequent references to Lincoln’s endorsement of
“ethnic cleansing” and a “final solution” to the
race problem, and his diatribe becomes almost impossible
to take seriously. The wonder of it all is that Bennett
consulted not only Lincoln’s own speeches and
writings, but also a host of primary and secondary
sources that should have cleared up much of his
confusion about Lincoln’s approach to slavery under
the Constitution. Here, more was not better. Bennett
allows Lincoln’s rivals to second-guess Lincoln’s
own explanations for what he was attempting to do as
president of a republic during a rebellion. Bennett’s
attempt to understand Lincoln’s principles and
policies regarding American slavery falters on so many
fronts that we will focus on the greatest
misunderstandings, especially as they pertain to the
American form and practice of self-government.
Although
Frederick Douglass heads the list of “real
emancipators” on his dedication page, Bennett quotes
selectively from his “Oration in Memory of Abraham
Lincoln” (1876). To portray Douglass as a tepid
supporter of Lincoln, Bennett violates his own
admonition against “the fallacy of the isolated
quote” by highlighting only criticisms of Lincoln by
the famous abolitionist speaker. Douglass does say that
Lincoln “was preeminently the white man’s President,
entirely devoted to the welfare of white men.” But
Bennett omits several passages that show Douglass’s
more sober and deliberate assessment of Lincoln.
Speaking as an escaped slave, Douglass remarks that
under Lincoln’s “wise and beneficent rule we saw
ourselves gradually lifted from the depths of slavery to
the heights of liberty and manhood.” Unlike Bennett,
Douglass praises the Emancipation Proclamation as “the
immortal paper, which, though, special in its language,
was general in its principles and effect, making slavery
forever impossible in the United States.”
Douglass
goes on to conclude that if Lincoln “put the abolition
of slavery before the salvation of the Union, he would
have inevitably driven from him a powerful class of the
American people and rendered resistance to rebellion
impossible.” Viewed from the abolitionist ranks,
“Mr. Lincoln seemed tardy, cold, dull, and
indifferent; but measuring him by the sentiment of his
country, a sentiment he was bound as a statesman to
consult, he was swift, zealous, radical, and
determined.”
It’s
as if Douglass grows in his understanding of Lincoln’s
statesmanship as the speech progresses. But Bennett
sours from the very beginning, unable to appreciate with
Douglass the great difficulty of Lincoln’s task and
the nobility of what he ultimately accomplished.
Bennett
also dedicates his book to a couple of “radical
humanitarians,” John Brown and Wendell Phillips.
(Bennett crosses abolitionist extraordinaire William
Lloyd Garrison off his list because he became a Lincoln
supporter during the 1864 election.) These so-called
freedom-lovers sought to free Americans by preaching
against the limitations of constitutional
self-government and free elections. Bennett admits these
and other abolitionists “inflame” public opinion and
“create contempt” for the Constitution, but he
applauds them for it because of the purity of their
motives.
Upon
finding several of Lincoln’s contemporaries
complaining of his contempt for abolitionists, Bennett
concludes that Lincoln did not, in today’s parlance,
“feel the slaves’ pain.” A better indication of
Lincoln’s personal feelings regarding the plight of
American slaves, however, can be found in an 1855 letter
he wrote to his best friend, Joshua F. Speed: “I
confess I hate to see the poor creatures hunted down,
and caught, and carried back to their stripes, and
unrewarded toils; but I bite my lip and keep quiet.”
Lincoln also reminded Speed, a Kentucky slaveholder who
professed “the abstract wrong” of slavery, of the
shackled slaves they saw onboard a steamboat they rode
in 1841: “That sight was a continual torment to me.”
Lincoln then explained that he and most Northerners
“do crucify their feelings, in order to maintain their
loyalty to the constitution and the Union.”
Lincoln’s refusal to join the abolitionist cause,
therefore, derived not from callous indifference toward
the slave but from principled devotion to the American
regime -- a form of government that would extend its
protection of freedom as far as the governed would
allow. As he put it to his long-time friend, “I also
acknowledge your rights and my obligations, under the
constitution, in regard to your slaves.” Lincoln, in
short, distinguished his personal sentiments from his
political responsibility regarding a subject that had
“the power of making me miserable.”
Simply
put, Lincoln’s hesitation to emancipate slaves during
the Civil War derived from his recognition that the
American experiment in self-government was in danger.
“We already have an important principle to rally and
unite the people in the fact that constitutional
government is at stake,” he wrote. “This is a
fundamental idea, going down about as deep as any
thing.” Lincoln was at pains to figure out how to
preserve a constitutional regime from the physical force
of rebellious southerners as well as the rhetorical
force of rebellious abolitionist: the former were
unwilling to obey a duly elected Republican
administration, while the latter were unwilling to
support a constitutional union of freemen and
slaveholders. To act simply according to an abstract
truth about the natural equality of human beings -- by
proclaiming the natural injustice of slavery -- without
acting as well in accordance with the coeval truth that
government can act legitimately only by the consent of
the governed would be to subvert the very form of
government and law-abiding habits that make for a free
society.
The
Constitution vests limited powers in the three branches
of the national government. This was always Lincoln's
understanding, and one he reiterated at the outset of
his First Inaugural Address as it pertained to slavery
in the South. “I have no purpose, directly or
indirectly, to interfere with the institution of slavery
in the States where it exists,” he said. “I believe
I have no lawful right to do so.” The Constitution
restricted what Lincoln as president could do about
“the peculiar institution,” and as the most
deliberate and settled will of the American people, the
Constitution stood as the political lodestar for
Lincoln.
Upon
what authority, then, did he proclaim freedom to slaves
in the South almost two years later? As the final
Emancipation Proclamation states it: “by virtue of the
power in me vested as Commander-in-Chief, of the Army
and Navy of the United States in time of actual armed
rebellion against authority and government of the United
States, and as a fit and necessary war measure for
suppressing said rebellion.” The nation had moved from
peace to war since his inauguration, which legitimated
his war-making authority; in addition, Lincoln judged
that the uneven progress of the war now called for
eliminating the support that slavery gave to the
southern war effort.
In
his preliminary Emancipation Proclamation, Lincoln
emphasized that his war aim had not changed:
“hereafter, as heretofore, the war will be prosecuted
for the object of practically restoring the
constitutional relation between the United States, and
each of the states, and the people thereof, in which
states that relation is, or may be, suspended, or
disturbed.” Thus, he wanted the nation to understand
his war-time emancipation proclamation not as a mere
exercise of will or force on behalf of a moral objective
but as a military measure in accord with his
constitutional oath to uphold the laws in all the
states.
Lincoln
gave the clearest statement of his intention as
president and commander-in-chief regarding slavery and
the war effort in response to a public letter by New
York Tribune editor Horace Greeley. "My
paramount object in this struggle is to save the union,
and is not either to save or to destroy slavery,”
Lincoln wrote. “If I could save the Union without
freeing any slave, I would do it; and if I could save it
by freeing all the slaves, I would do it; and if I could
save it by freeing some and leaving others alone I would
also do that.” Of course, he led the nation through
all three scenarios by the time of his second
inauguration, at which point the 13th Amendment had been
approved by Congress and was on the way to state
ratification by year’s end.
Lincoln’s
devotion to the constitutional union took precedence
over the abolition of slavery, but in a way that set the
nation back on course to ridding itself of slavery.
Miss this, as Bennett does from cover to cover, and you
misunderstand the Emancipation Proclamation and its
connection to the Union war effort.
This
priority reflected Lincoln’s concern for finding
legitimate ways to put down the rebellion without losing
the allegiance of unionist southerners, some of whom
included slave-owners who had a constitutional right to
own slaves that Lincoln as president was sworn to
uphold. As William C. Harris shows in With
Charity for All: Lincoln and the Restoration of the
Union (1997), “war-time reconstruction was
designed to initiate the restoration of civil
self-government in the South.” Harris reminds us that
Lincoln’s expressed war aim was to quash he rebellion
without “depriving Unionists of their constitutional
rights” or “making it more difficult for them to
cooperate in the restoration of loyal governments in the
South.” Lincoln’s apparent hesitation to free slaves
simply cannot be understood without a clear
understanding of his constitutional obligations, which
Bennett summarily overlooks.
Bennett
also claims that Lincoln deliberately undermined the
Emancipation Proclamation by its selective application:
“What Lincoln did — and it was so clever that we
ought to stop calling him honest Abe — was to
‘free’ slaves in Confederate-held territory where he
couldn’t free them and to leave them in slavery in
Union-held territory where he could have freed them.”
This argument implies that what Lincoln should have done
regarding slavery concerned only military might, and not
constitutional right. But Lincoln omitted the so-called
“border slave states” of Missouri, Kentucky,
Maryland, and Delaware from the Emancipation
Proclamation because they were not in rebellion against
the federal government and therefore its citizens
deserved the full protection of their constitutional
rights.
The
explicit exceptions Lincoln made of southern,
slave-holding areas under Union-army control prior to
January 1, 1863 (i.e., the counties constituting West
Virginia and portions of Virginia and Louisiana) also
fall under this category. When Secretary of the Treasury
Salmon P. Chase argued for applying the Emancipation
Proclamation to the exempted areas of Virginia and
Louisiana, Lincoln replied he could only do so
“without the argument of military necessity, and so,
without any argument, except the one that I think the
measure politically expedient, and morally right.” He
added, “Would I not give up all footing upon the
constitution or law? Would I not thus be in the
boundless field of absolutism?”
Lincoln
shows that a president, even acting as
commander-in-chief, must exercise authority not as a
dictator — benevolent or otherwise — but within the
limits set forth by the Constitution. Lincoln wanted to
rid the nation of slavery, but not at the price of free
government.
As
for the claim that the Emancipation Proclamation was a
dead letter to slaves behind Confederate lines, Lincoln
committed “the Executive government of the United
States, including the military and naval authorities
thereof,” to “recognize and maintain the freedom of
said persons.” Slaves escaping from their rebellious
masters would no longer be viewed as fugitives from
justice but receive legal protection of their freedom by
the national government. For Bennett, this amounts to an
empty promise because the slaves were free only on paper
and not in practice. But what alternative was there for
slaves behind enemy lines?
As
Lincoln himself admitted only nine days before his
preliminary proclamation: “Would my word free the
slaves, when I cannot even enforce the Constitution in
the rebel states?” He therefore waited for a Union
victory as a sign that as commander-in-chief he could
back ink on paper with swords on the battlefield. (For
the definitive exposition of the Emancipation
Proclamation, see George Anastaplo's chapter on it in Abraham
Lincoln: A Constitutional Biography [1999].)
Bennett
chides Lincoln for promoting gradual, compensated
emancipation and the colonization of freedmen as the
means of achieving his dream of a “lily-white
America.” In this context, the preliminary
Emancipation Proclamation, announced 100 days before its
implementation on January 1, 1863, was merely a ruse,
Bennett asserts, to delay emancipation until Lincoln
could persuade Congress to “deport” all blacks from
the United States. To be sure, Lincoln favored gradual
emancipation as well as colonization of blacks, but not
because he was a white supremacist. Although he
recognized the manifest injustice of slavery, he also
believed that emancipation was always at best only half
the battle. As Anastaplo observes, one then had to
devise a way for former masters and former slaves to
live with each other as free men.
On
this question, Lincoln was neither sanguine nor alone in
the recognition that slavery’s demise “was piled
high with difficulty.” That most famous foreign
observer of the American republic, Alexis de Tocqueville,
wrote in Democracy
in America (1835) that “it is impossible to
foresee a time when blacks and whites will come to
mingle and derive the same benefits from society.”
Moreover, American slavery had so poisoned each race’s
view of the other that if blacks continued to
concentrate in the South, “sooner or later in the
southern states white and blacks must come to blows.”
This conclusion of a disinterested commentator on the
American regime makes Lincoln’s support of
colonization less a reflection of racism than a sober
consideration of the social and political reality of his
day.
Tocqueville
noted, “In antiquity the most difficult thing was to
change the law; in the modern world the hard thing is to
alter mores, and our difficulty begins where theirs
ended.” If American mores were such that American
democracy could not avoid this coming clash of erstwhile
enemies, former white masters versus former black
slaves, then Lincoln along with Henry Clay and other
colonizationists may not have been the most optimistic
republicans. But they could hardly be faulted for
attempting to prevent a regional race war that might
tear the entire nation and its experiment in
self-government into pieces. Bennett makes no allowance
for sensible and learned men like Lincoln to believe
that American blacks and whites en masse simply would
not live peaceably with each other at the close of an
oppressive history. The racial divide still present in
America today confirms the difficulty Lincoln,
Tocqueville, and others anticipated when former slave
owners and former slaves, and their descendants,
continued to reside in the same territory.
Bennett’s
exercise in exasperation over Lincoln as the Great
Emancipator displays his woeful ignorance about the
principles and practices of American self- government.
Lacking even a rudimentary grasp of how the ideas of
human equality and the consent of the governed inform
the constitutional operation of the American government,
it’s no wonder Bennett is unable to grasp Lincoln’s
political prudence. Bennett concludes, “There is thus
nothing we can learn from Abraham Lincoln about race
relations, except what not to say or do.” By reading Forced
Into Glory, one learns nothing from Lerone Bennett
about the requirements of statesmanship within a
constitutional democracy. With Lincoln as his tutor
instead of his target, you would think he might have
learned something.
Adjunct
Fellow Lucas E. Morel is Assistant Professor of Politics
at Washington and Lee University and author of Lincoln’s
Sacred Effort: Defining Religion's Role in American
Self-Government (Lexington Books, 2000).
Subscribe
to the Claremont Institute's Precepts to receive the
latest news and information about national politics and
other topics via e-mail.
All pages copyright © 2000 The
Claremont Institute